Updated relations and mkdocs.yaml
This commit is contained in:
parent
0d1559b79d
commit
53ccc99fc2
3 changed files with 107 additions and 3 deletions
|
@ -9,9 +9,21 @@ theme:
|
|||
- navigation.tabs
|
||||
- toc.follow
|
||||
palette:
|
||||
- scheme: slate
|
||||
- media: "(prefers-color-scheme: light)"
|
||||
scheme: default
|
||||
primary: white
|
||||
accent: teal
|
||||
toggle:
|
||||
icon: material/brightness-7
|
||||
name: Switch to dark mode
|
||||
|
||||
- media: "(prefers-color-scheme: dark)"
|
||||
scheme: slate
|
||||
primary: black
|
||||
accent: teal
|
||||
toggle:
|
||||
icon: material/brightness-3
|
||||
name: Switch to light mode
|
||||
language: en
|
||||
|
||||
extra:
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -9,9 +9,21 @@ theme:
|
|||
- navigation.tabs
|
||||
- toc.follow
|
||||
palette:
|
||||
- scheme: slate
|
||||
- media: "(prefers-color-scheme: light)"
|
||||
scheme: default
|
||||
primary: white
|
||||
accent: teal
|
||||
toggle:
|
||||
icon: material/brightness-7
|
||||
name: Schakel naar dark mode
|
||||
|
||||
- media: "(prefers-color-scheme: dark)"
|
||||
scheme: slate
|
||||
primary: black
|
||||
accent: teal
|
||||
toggle:
|
||||
icon: material/brightness-3
|
||||
name: Schakel naar light mode
|
||||
language: nl
|
||||
|
||||
extra:
|
||||
|
|
|
@ -1,5 +1,7 @@
|
|||
# Relations
|
||||
|
||||
## Binary relations
|
||||
|
||||
> *Definition*: a binary relation $R$ between the sets $S$ and $T$ is a subset of the Cartesian product $S \times T$.
|
||||
>
|
||||
> * If $(a,b) \in R$ then $a$ is in relation $R$ to $b$, denoted by $aRb$.
|
||||
|
@ -77,4 +79,82 @@ Some relations have special properties
|
|||
|
||||
Let $\Pi_R$ be the set of $R$-equivalence classes. Then by reflexivity of $R$ we find that each element $a \in S$ is inside the class $[a]_R$ of $\Pi_R$. If an element $a \in S$ is in the classes $[b]_R$ and $[c]_R$ of $\Pi_R$, then by the previous lemma we find $[b]_R = [a]_R$ and $[c]_R = [a]_R$. Then $[b]_R = [c]_R$, therefore each element $a \in S$ is inside a unique member of $\Pi_R$, which therefore is a partition of $S$.
|
||||
|
||||
<br>
|
||||
<br>
|
||||
|
||||
## Composition of relations
|
||||
|
||||
If $R_1$ and $R_2$ are two relations between a set $S$ and $T$, new relations can be formed between $S$ and $T$ by taking the intersection $R_1 \cap R_2$, the union $R_1 \cup R_2$ or the complement $R_1 \backslash R_2$. Furthermore a relation $R^\top$ from $T$ to $S$ can be considered as the relation $\{(t,s) \in T \times S \;|\; (s,t) \in R\}$ and the identity relation from $T$ to $S$ is given by $I = \{(s, t) \in S \times T \;|\; s = t\}$
|
||||
|
||||
Another way of making new relations out of existing ones is by taking the composition.
|
||||
|
||||
> *Definition*: if $R_1$ is a relation between $S$ and $T$ and $R_2$ is a relation between $T$ and $U$ then the composition $R = R_1;R_2$ is the relation between $S$ and $U$ defined by $sRu$ for $s \in S$ and $u \in U$, if and only if there is a $t \in T$ with $sR_1t$ and $tR_2u$.
|
||||
|
||||
<br>
|
||||
|
||||
> *Proposition*: suppose $R_1$ is relation from $S$ to $T$, $R_2$ a relation from $T$ to $U$ and $R_3$ a relation from $U$ to $V$. Then $R_1;(R_2;R_3) = (R_1;R_2);R_3$. Composing relations is associative.
|
||||
|
||||
??? note "*Proof*:"
|
||||
|
||||
Suppose $s \in S$ and $v \in V$ with $sR_1;(R_2;R_3)v$. Then a $t \in T$ with $sR_1t$ and $t(R_2;R_3)v$ can be found. Then there is also a $u \in U$ with $tR_2u$ and $uR_3v$. For this $u$ there is $sR_1;R_2u$ and $uR_3v$ and hence $s(R_1;R_2);R_3v$.
|
||||
|
||||
Similarly, if $s \in S$ and $v \in V$ with $s(R_1;R_2);R_3v$. Then a $u \in U$ with $s(R_1;R_2)u$ and $uR_3v$ can be found. Then there is also a $t \in T$ with $sR_1t$ and $tR_2u$. For this $t$ there is $tR_2;R_3u$ and $sR_1t$ and hence $sR_1;(R_2;R_3)v$.
|
||||
|
||||
<br>
|
||||
|
||||
## Transitive closure
|
||||
|
||||
> *Lemma*: let $\ell$ be a collection of relations $R$ on a set $S$. If all relations $R$ in $\ell$ are transitive, reflexive or symmetric then the relation $\bigcap_{R \in \ell} R$ is also transitive, reflexive or symmetric respectively.
|
||||
|
||||
??? note "*Proof*:"
|
||||
|
||||
Let $\bar R = \bigcap_{R \in \ell} R$. Suppose all members of $\ell$ are transitive. Then for all $a,b,c \in S$ with $a \bar R b$ and $b \bar R c$ there is $aRb$ and $bRc$ for all $R \in \ell$. Thus by transitivity of each $R \in \ell$ there is also $aRc$ for each $R \in \ell$. Thus there is $a \bar R c$. Hence $\bar R$ is also transitive.
|
||||
|
||||
Proof for symmetric relation will follow.
|
||||
|
||||
Proof for reflexive relation will follow.
|
||||
|
||||
The above lemma makes it possible to define the reflexive, symmetric or transitive closure of a relation $R$ on a set $S$. It is the smallest reflexive, symmetric or transitive relation containing $R$.
|
||||
|
||||
For example suppose $R = \{(1,2), (2,2), (2,3), (5,4)\}$ is a relation on $S = \{1, 2, 3, 4, 5\}$.
|
||||
|
||||
: The reflexive closure of $R$ is then the relation
|
||||
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\big\{(1,1), (1,2), (2,2), (2,3), (3,3), (4,4), (5,5), (5,4) \big\},
|
||||
$$
|
||||
|
||||
the symmetric closure of $R$ is then the relation
|
||||
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\big\{ (1,2), (2,1), (2,2), (2,3), (3,2), (4,5), (5,4) \big\},
|
||||
$$
|
||||
|
||||
and the transitive clusure of $R$ is then the relation
|
||||
|
||||
$$
|
||||
\{(1,2), (1,3), (2,2), (2,3), (5,4)\}.
|
||||
$$
|
||||
|
||||
It may be observed that the reflexive closure of $R$ equals the relation $I \cup R$ and the symmetric closure equals $R \cup R^\top$. For the transitive closure there is:
|
||||
|
||||
> *Proposition*: $\bigcup_{n > 0} R^n$ is the transitive closure of the relation $R$ on a set $S$.
|
||||
|
||||
??? note "*Proof*:"
|
||||
|
||||
Define $\bar R = \bigcup_{n>0} R^n$, to show that $\bar R$ is the least transitive relation containing $R$, $\bar R$ must contain $R$, must be transitive and must be the smallest set with both of those properties.
|
||||
|
||||
Since $R \subseteq \bar R$, $\bar R$ contains all of the $R^i, i \in \mathbb{N}$, so in particular $\bar R$ contains $R$.
|
||||
|
||||
If $(s_1, s_2), (s_2, s_3) \in \bar R$, then $(s_1, s_2) \in R^j$ and $(s_2, s_3) \in R^k$ for some $j,k$. Since composition is [associative](#composition-of-relations), $R^{j+k} = R^j ; R^k$ and hence $(s_1, s_3) \in R^{j+k} \subseteq \bar R$.
|
||||
|
||||
We claim that if $T$ is any transitive relation containing $R$, then $\bar R \subseteq T$. By taking $R^n \subseteq \bar R \subseteq T \; \forall n \in \mathbb{N}$ .
|
||||
|
||||
: We first check for $n=1$
|
||||
|
||||
$$
|
||||
R^1 = R \subseteq T.
|
||||
$$
|
||||
|
||||
: Now suppose that for some $k \in \mathbb{N}$ we have $R^k \subseteq T$. Then by assumption $R^{k+1} \subseteq T$. Let $(s_1, s_3) \in R^{k+1} = R^k ; R$, then $(s_1, s_2) \in R$ and $(s_2, s_3) \in R^k$ for some $s_2$. Hence $(s_1, s_2), (s_2, s_3) \in T$ and by transitivity of $T$, $(s_1, s_3) \in T$.
|
||||
|
||||
Hence if the claim holds for some $k \in \mathbb{N}$ then it also holds for $k+1$. The principle of natural induction implies now that $\forall n \in \mathbb{N}$ we have $R^n \subseteq \bar R \subseteq T$.
|
Loading…
Reference in a new issue